20
Understanding Marx’s theory of value: an assessment of a controversy MURRAY E.G. SMITH University ofManitoba* Trois ecoles principalrs de theorie de valeur mamienne sont identifiees et situees par rapport a des sujets essentiels oh il existe une controverse en matiere de valeur, en particulier le postulat que le travail vital est l’unique source de valeur nouvelle. L’effondrement de la theorie de valeur de 1’Ccole ‘orthodoxe’ (Ricardo-marxiste) est attribuee aux raisonnement errone d’une conceptualisation de la valeur de ‘travail exprime,’ une approche rejetee de la m&me facon par les theoriciens de la valeur ‘neo-orthodoxe’ et ‘fondamentaliste’. Cependant la comparaison des ecoles neo-orthodoxe et fondamentaliste revele que seule cette derniere est compatible avec les objectifs et les postulats essentiels de la theorie de Marx. En m&me temps, on indique que l’approche fondamentaliste ne peut &re soutenue que par un engagement explicite a l’idee que le travail abstrait (essence-m6me de la valeur) existe en tant qu’universel structure1 specifique au capitalisme. Three major schools of Marxian value theory are identified and situated in respect to some pivotal issues of the value controversy, in particular the postulate that living labour is the sole source of new value. The collapse of the ‘orthodox’ (Ricardian-Marxist) school of value theory is attributed to the fallacies of an ‘embodied labour’ conceptualization of value, an approach which has been rejected by ‘neo-orthodox’ and ‘fundamentalist’value theorists alike. However a comparison of the neo-orthodox and fundamentalist schools reveals that only the latter remains consistent with the objectives and essential postulates of Marx’s theory. At the same time, it is argued that the fundamentalist approach can only be sustained through an explicit commitment to the idea that abstract labour (as the ‘substance’ of value) exists as a structural ‘universal’ specific to capitalism. * I wish to thank David Schweitzer, Blanca Muratorio, Bob Ratner, Bob Chernomas and Derek Sayer for their helpful comments on an earlier elaboration of the ideas developed in this article (Smith, 1989).Thanks are also due to two anonymous CHSA reviewers and to Jim Curtis for a number of suggestions that have significantly strengthened the final product. The argument presented here is based on work which I carried out whilst in receipt of fund- ing from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. This article was received in August, 1989 and accepted in December, 1990. Canad. Rev. SOC. 81 Anth. I Rev. canad. SOC. & Anth. 28(3) 1991

Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

Understanding Marx’s theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

MURRAY E.G. SMITH University ofManitoba*

Trois ecoles principalrs de theorie de valeur mamienne sont identifiees et situees par rapport a des sujets essentiels oh il existe une controverse en matiere de valeur, en particulier le postulat que le travail vital est l’unique source de valeur nouvelle. L’effondrement de la theorie de valeur de 1’Ccole ‘orthodoxe’ (Ricardo-marxiste) est attribuee aux raisonnement errone d’une conceptualisation de la valeur de ‘travail exprime,’ une approche rejetee de la m&me facon par les theoriciens de la valeur ‘neo-orthodoxe’ et ‘fondamentaliste’. Cependant la comparaison des ecoles neo-orthodoxe et fondamentaliste revele que seule cette derniere est compatible avec les objectifs et les postulats essentiels de la theorie de Marx. En m&me temps, on indique que l’approche fondamentaliste ne peut &re soutenue que par un engagement explicite a l’idee que le travail abstrait (essence-m6me de la valeur) existe en tant qu’universel structure1 specifique au capitalisme.

Three major schools of Marxian value theory are identified and situated in respect to some pivotal issues of the value controversy, in particular the postulate that living labour is the sole source of new value. The collapse of the ‘orthodox’ (Ricardian-Marxist) school of value theory is attributed to the fallacies of an ‘embodied labour’ conceptualization of value, an approach which has been rejected by ‘neo-orthodox’ and ‘fundamentalist’ value theorists alike. However a comparison of the neo-orthodox and fundamentalist schools reveals that only the latter remains consistent with the objectives and essential postulates of Marx’s theory. At the same time, it is argued that the fundamentalist approach can only be sustained through an explicit commitment to the idea that abstract labour (as the ‘substance’ of value) exists as a structural ‘universal’ specific to capitalism.

* I wish to thank David Schweitzer, Blanca Muratorio, Bob Ratner, Bob Chernomas and Derek Sayer for their helpful comments on an earlier elaboration of the ideas developed in this article (Smith, 1989). Thanks are also due to two anonymous CHSA reviewers and to Jim Curtis for a number of suggestions that have significantly strengthened the final product. The argument presented here is based on work which I carried out whilst in receipt of fund- ing from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. This article was received in August, 1989 and accepted in December, 1990.

Canad. Rev. SOC. 81 Anth. I Rev. canad. SOC. & Anth. 28(3) 1991

Page 2: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

358 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

The purpose of this article is to provide an overview and critical assessment of the controversy among Marxist and neo-Marxist theorists concerning the content, probity and implications of Marx’s theory of value. Like many of the controversies that have attended the revival of Western Marxism over the past 20 years, the ‘value controversy’ attests to the willingness of con- temporary Marxists to entertain a variety of interpretations of Marx’s theoretical legacy and even to part company with him on issues of the ut- most importance. Unfortunately it also testifies to the capacity of Marxists to debate such issues in a fashion which renders them relatively inaccessible to the non-specialist. In consideration of this problem, I shall try to ‘inter- pret’ Marx’s value theory and the controversy surrounding it in such a way as to highlight what I take to be the key postulates of the capitalist law of labour-value. Hopefully this will contribute not only to a better under- standing of some of the contested issues but also to a clarification of what is at stake in this controversy, something which is too rarely discussed by its participants.

The principal idea defended in the article is that Marx’s theory of value constitutes the unity of a qualitative treatment of the value-form (exchange- value/money-price) and a quantitative concern with the ‘substance of value’. The conceptual nexus of this theory is seen to be ‘abstract labour’ - a cate- gory which bridges the divide between value’s ‘particular’ and ‘universal’ aspects. Key to such an interpretation is an extension of the ontological ‘re- versals’ described by Mam in his discussion of the value-form to include the relation between abstract labour as a real universal structure and commodi- ties as sensuously concrete particulars. Such a conceptualization furnishes a much-needed ontological and methodological basis for sustaining the key postulates of what I call the ‘fundamentalist school’ of Marxian value theory as against the perspectives of a ‘neo-orthodox school’ which has stripped Marx’s value theory of much of its ‘operational’ significance. These fun- damentalist postulates, I argue, pertain to the laws of motion of the capital- ist economy as a whole, and it is therefore a mistake for those who defend them to pursue a theoretical agenda which tilts Marx’s value theory in the direction of accounting for ‘relative equilibrium prices’ (a project having little to do with disclosing the historical-structural limits of capitalism).

The paper is divided into four parts. Part I attempts to identify the key postulates of Marx’s theory of value and to suggest their importance to his overall theoretical project. Part I1 addresses some of the major issues that have figured in the ‘value controversy’ and situates three major schools of Marxian value theory in relation to them. Part 111 explores some of the methodological and ontological questions which divide these schools, while Part IV gives a brief elaboration of the substantive theoretical implications of Marx’s value theory for a scientific analysis of capitalism.

I ELEMENTS OF MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

If it is possible to reduce the several thousand pages of the many books and manuscripts comprising Marx’s ‘critique of political economy’ to a single theme, it is surely this: for Marx, the capitalist mode of production (and,

Page 3: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

359 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

inter alia, its ‘law of motion’) is not ‘eternal’ but subject to specifiable his- torical limits which it is a task of science to disclose. According to one in- fluential and eminently plausible interpretation of Mam, these limits are precisely those of the capitalist law of value, as an historically-specific ex- pression of a more general ‘law of human labor-time’ (Marx, 1973: 173; Col- letti, 1972: 91-92), to bring about a systematic increase in the productive capacities of humankind and therewith progress in the development of human culture. In other words Marx’s project in his critique of political economy is to specify, on the basis of his theory of value, how and why capi- talist relations of production must become fetters on the development of the forces of production.

Such a project has little to do with analysing how ‘individual prices’ are constituted; and it should therefore be apparent that Marx’s value theory has a quite different agenda and content than those ‘value theories’ that are directly theories of price. From the outset, then, it should be emphasized that Marx does not follow neo-classical (or much of classical) economics in treating ‘price,’ ‘exchange value’ and ‘value’ as interchangeable or synony- mous terms.

Marx’s ‘Concept’ of Value Marx provides what is perhaps the clearest statement of the distinctive pro- cedure he followed in elaborating his theory of value in Notes on Adolph Wagner, a short polemical work written late in his career:

Herr Wagner forgets that neither ‘value’ nor ‘exchange value’ are my subjects, but the commodity ... In the first place I do not start out from ‘concepts’, hence I do not start out from the ‘concept of value’, and do not have ‘to divide’ these in any way. What I start out from [in Capital] is the simplest social form in which the labour-product is presented in contemporary society, and this is the ‘commod- ity’. I analyze it, and right from the beginning, in the form in which it appears. Here I find that it is, on the one hand, in its natural form, a useful thing, alias a use-value; on the other hand, it is a bearer of exchange-value, and from this view- point, it is itself ‘exchange-value’. Further analysis of the latter shows me that ex- change-value is only a ‘form of appearance’, the autonomous mode of presentation of the value contained in the commodity, and then I move on to the analysis of the latter ... Hence I do not divide value into use-value and exchange value as antitheses into which the abstraction ‘value’ splits, rather [I divide] the concrete social form of the labour-product; ‘commodity’ is, on the one hand, use- value, and on the other hand, ‘value’, not exchange-value, since the mere form of appearance is not its proper content (1989: 4142).

This brief passage possesses the greatest methodological significance for an appreciation of Mam’s theory of value. On the one hand, Mam empha- sizes his concern with the question of ‘forms’ and their analysis - as well as with the relationship between forms and their ‘content’. On the other hand,

Page 4: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

360 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

he insists that the starting point of his theory is not ‘conceptual’ (an ideal abstraction), but something real, something which evidently can be re- garded as having both a ‘natural form’ and a ‘social form’ - the individual commodity, what might be considered a ‘real abstraction’.

If the concepts of use-value and exchange-value are ‘determined’ by the abstract qualities of a real object, however, it cannot be said that they are themselves entirely determinant of what must follow in the analysis of the commodity. Classical political economy, no less than Marx, recognized that a commodity is characterized by both ‘value in use’ and ‘value in exchange’; but this recognition did not lead the classical economists to the same con- clusions about the commodity-capitalist economy that Marx drew. Indeed, even the Marx of The Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy of 1859 had yet to break with that tradition’s conceptual conflation of ‘value’ and ‘exchange value’. What, then, led him to do so?

Consider the following passage from Marx’s 1868 letter to Kugelmann: ‘the form in which [the] proportional distribution of labour asserts itself [as a “natural law” stemming from “the necessity of the distribution of social labour in definite proportions”], in a state of society where the interconnec- tion of social labour is manifested in the private exchange of the individual products of labour, is precisely the exchange-value of these products’ (1965: 209). The concept of ‘exchange-value’ in this passage is unmistakably that of a specific social form of a general human imperative to distribute aggre- gate social labour in definite proportions - a form peculiar to a society where the medium of ‘interconnection’ amongst different units of social labour is the indirect one of private exchange.

However, exchange-value is also a concept derived from the analysis of the ‘individual commodity,’ which, according to the opening sentence of Capital I , is itself the ‘elementary form’ of ‘the wealth of societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails’ (1977: 125). Thus, while the ‘in- dividual commodity’ has characteristics which are readily observable, it is also the ‘elementary form’ of something greater than itself: the ‘immense collection of commodities’ which is the ‘appearance’ of wealth in capitalist societies.

Taking stock, the concept of exchange-value arises from the analysis of the individual commodity, as a form-characteristic of what turns out to be both a concrete object with a real (natural and social) content and an ‘elementary form’ of something larger than itself. The form-content distinc- tion in this context is unmistakably aligned with - and a special case of - the distinction between the general (or universal) and the particular. As a particular incarnation of a general class of objects called commodities, the individual commodity is both a real concrete object and a manifestation of the abstract characteristics of all commodities.

Once the focus of analysis shifts from the ‘individual commodity’ to the mutual interconnections of all commodities, it becomes necessary to deploy a different ‘concept’ from that of exchange-value - a more ‘general’ or ‘uni- versal’ concept which captures the characteristics of commodities no longer perceived as discrete things in themselves, but as a ‘collection’ of products

Page 5: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

361 MAFX’S THEORY OF VALUE

of labour, whose existence is necessarily a collective one. Does this suggest that ‘value’ has a purely ‘mental’ existence - that it ex-

ists merely as an ‘intellectual aid’? Not at all. But to understand the nature of the ‘real existence’ of value is to go to the heart of Marx’s theory of value; it is to anticipate the question of the ‘ontology of value’. We are not yet in a position to address this question. Yet, as an ‘intellectual aid’ to under- standing what follows, it is as well to bear in mind that for Marx the ex- change-value of a commodity stands in a specific relation to its value: as form to content.

Form and Content As a material expression and individual manifestation of a social division and distribution of labour carried out ‘unconsciously,’ behind the backs of private commodity producers, the commodity is unavoidably implicated in ‘value relations’ and is, in this sense, a ‘crystal’ of value, understood as a ‘social substance’. But the ‘form of appearance’ of the commodity’s value (that is to say, of its relationship to the larger social process of forcibly ar- ticulating a division and distribution of labour between various branches of production) is necessarily its forms of exchangeability with other products, i.e. its exchange-value(s1. As a ‘value’ the commodity is conceived in abstrac- tion from its use-value, as the embodiment of a definite fraction of the aggre- gate social labour employed in the production of all commodities; and it is this which makes ‘value’ the common factor underlying the different ex- change-values that the individual commodity can manifest.

Depending upon the angle from which one approaches the problem, value can be conceived as the ‘content’ or ‘substance’ of exchange-value, or as the ‘form’ assumed by the division of labour under determinate social relations of production. ‘Value’ may be defined as ‘a representation in objects, an ob- jective expression, of a relation between men, a social relation, the relation- ship of men to their reciprocal productive activity’ (Marx 1975, III: 147) or as ‘a definite social mode of existence of human activity (labour)’ (Marx 1978a, I: 461, which must assume the phenomenal form of exchange-value. As I. Rubin puts it: ‘value is “reified”, “materialized” labor and simul- taneously it is an expression of production relations among people’ (1973: 153). Rubin explains this apparent ‘contradiction’ as follows: ‘The two defi- nitions of value contradict each other if one deals with physiological labor; but they perfectly supplement each other if one deals with social labor. Ab- stract labour [the substance of value1 and value have a social and not a mate- rial-technical or physiological nature’ (ibid.).’

The Significance of Marx’s Method What Rubin points to here is the necessity for an adequate appreciation of the method underlying Marx’s ‘forms analysis’. As he rightly insists, ‘[the] process of development of forms in their various phases’ can only be prop- erly explored through a genetic-dialectical method, which considers the developmental and contradictory relations among things. Crucially, such an

Page 6: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

362 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

approach is associated with an ‘internal’ conception of the formlcontent re- lation:

One cannot forget that on the question of the relation between content and form, Marx took the standpoint of Hegel and not of Kant. Kant treated form as some- thing external in relation to the content, as something which adheres to the con- tent from the outside. From the standpoint of Hegel’s philosophy, the content is not in itself something to which form adheres from the outside. Rather, through its development, the content itself gives birth to the form which is already latent in the content. Form necessarily grows from the content itself (1973: 117).

The point of all this is that the ‘dividing line’ between form and content is not at all a clear-cut issue. To understand how value can be both the ‘so- cial content’ of exchange-value and the ‘objective (or material) expression’ of the social relations existing between the productive activities of people requires an analysis of the form and the substance of value; and this is pre- cisely the way in which Marx proceeds. We shall return to these questions in Part 11; but first we need to consider the specificity of capitalist social re- lations and their role in defining the content of the law of value.

Capitalism and the Law of Value The law of value is a regulatory principle of an economy in which the pro- ducts of labour are produced for the purpose of private exchange. The social production relation which is fundamental to such ‘commodity production’ is the social equality of commodities and commodityproducers as well as the social equality and homogeneity of commodity-producing labour. The ‘egal- itarianism’ of this principle no more presupposes the abolition of vertical social differentiation or ‘ranking’ than it obviates the technically-hetero- geneous and differentially-skilled character of concrete ‘utility-shaping’ labours. What it does point to, however, is the idea of the ‘exchange of equiv- alents,’ to the normative imperative of maintaining a ‘level playing field’ in the sphere of exchange.

Under conditions of generalized (i.e. capitalist) commodity production, however, two other social production relations impact profoundly on the concrete operations of the law of value. These are l/ the exploitative relation existing between capital and wage-labour, and 21 the competitive relation which exists amongst individual private capitals (the latter relation encom- passing a tendency toward ‘monopolization’ or ‘oligopolization’ as a neces- sary outcome of competition).

If, following Rubin (19731, it is correct to view ‘value under capitalism’ as expressing the ensemble of these social production relations, then it should be apparent that the capitalist law of value must lead the capitalist mode of production to ‘move in contradiction’. The ‘contradictions’ of Marx’s theory are real contradictions, not ‘logical’ ones: they are conceptual reflections of the contradictory relations comprising the object under inves- tigation, namely a mode of production based on three distinct principles of

Page 7: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

363 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

social organization. To what then does Marx’s law of value refer? Unfortunately, Marx’s own

explicit ‘definition’ of this law is not particularly enlightening: ‘Whatever the manner in which the prices of various commodities are first mutually fured or regulated, their movements are always governed by the law of value. If the labour-time required for their production happens to shrink, prices fall; if it increases, prices rise, provided other conditions remain the same’ (1978b: 177). So formulated, it is hard to imagine anyone disagreeing with such a ‘law of labour-value’. But the substantive content of Marx’s law is actually both more contentious and far more interesting than this quota- tion suggests. A weak version of it is expressed in Morishima’s ‘Fundamen- tal Marxian Theorem,’ which states that positive surplus value (or a positive rate of surplus value) is a necessary and sufficient condition for the exist- ence of positive profits and a positive rate of profit (Morishima, 1973:6). Foley, among others, has furnished a stronger definition, according to which ‘the source of the value added of the mass of commodities produced is the labor expended in producing them’ (1986: 14, emphasis added). Couple this with Hilferding’s insistence that value exists as an ‘objective, quantitatively determined magnitude’ (1975: 159) and we arrive a t the propositions that living labour is the sole source of all new value and that value exists as a de- finite quantitative magnitude a t the level of the capitalist division of labour (or economy) as a whole.

These ‘fundamental postulates’ of Marx’s theory of value, which are shared by the apparently-contradictory analyses of Volumes One and Three of Capital, are the basis of Marx’s delineation of the ‘economic law of mo- tion’ of the capitalist mode of production.2 Marx’s theory of value as an analysis of the developmental tendencies of capitalism stands or falls with these postulates; so it is in respect to them that the controversy surround- ing this theory needs to be clarified and assessed.

I1 THE VALUE CONTROVERSY

It is common to distinguish between two aspects of Marx’s theory of value: one ‘qualitative’ and the other ‘quantitative’. This dichotomization has been defined differently by the various participants in the value controversy and has shifted over time (compare Sweezy, 1968 and Fine, 1986). Currently, the qualitative aspect of Marx’s theory tends to be identified with the complex of issues raised by Marx’s analysis of the ‘value-form’ in Chapter One of Capital I, while the quantitative aspect of the theory is associated with Marx’s ‘value-magnitude’ analyses, ranging from the discussion of ‘socially- necessary labour time’ in the first volume of Capital to the ‘transformation problem’ in the third.

In Chapter One of Capital I, Marx identifies the ‘substance’ of value as ‘abstract labour,’ defined as labour abstracted from its concrete utility-shap- ing characteristics and conceived as an aspect of the homogeneous mass of social labor entering into the production of commodities. The mcasure of this value-creating substance is socially-necessary labour time, defined as ‘the labour-time required to produce any use-value under the conditions of

Page 8: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

364 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

production normal for a given society and with the average degree of skill and intensity of labour prevalent in that society’ (1977: 129). It follows from this that: ‘The value of a commodity is related to the value of any other com- modity as the labour-time necessary for the production of the one is relat d to the labour-time necessary for the production of the other’ (1977: 130).

Marx’s subsequent analysis of exchange-value (or ‘the value form’) iden- tifies two ‘poles’ of the value relation, the ‘relative form’ of value and the ‘equivalent form’: ‘Whether a commodity is in the relative form or in its op- posite, the equivalent form, entirely depends on its actual position in the ex- pression of value. That is, it depends on whether it is the commodity whose value is being expressed, or the commodity in which value is being expressed’ (Marx, 1977: 140). Further analysis of this relation discloses three ‘peculi- arities’ of the equivalent form. First, ‘use-value becomes the form of appear- ance of its opposite, value’ (1977: 148) due to the fact that the physical body of the commodity standing in the equivalent form expresses the value of commodities standing in the relative form. It follows from this that the con- crete labour going into the production of this commodity stands in a rela- tion of equivalence to the abstract labour ‘embodied’ in the commodities standing in the relative form. Hence, ‘concrete labour becomes the form of manifestation of its opposite, abstract human labour’ (ibid.: 150). This leads directly to a third peculiarity: the equivalent form demonstrates that ‘pri- vate labour takes the form of its opposite, namely labour in its directly so- cial form’ (1977: 151).

The ‘reversals’ suggested in this analysis of the value form are of central importance to Marx’s whole value theory. Within value relations, Marx asserts, use value appears as value, concrete labour as abstract labour, and private labour as social labour. The commodity is a unity of use-value and value, but this dual character of the commodity is only expressed when its value has a form of appearance distinct from its natural (use-value) form. This form of appearance is its exchange-value. As the form of value, however, exchange value is subject to determinations beyond the sphere of produc- tion; it is subject to myriad ‘transformations’ capable of altering its magni- tude at the level of the individual commodity. One of these transformations concerns the influence of the equalizing tendency of profit rates upon the value form: the transformation of ‘commodity values’ (understood as ‘mone- tized values’ or ‘direct prices’ dictated solely by the commodity’s socially- necessary labour content) into ‘prices of production’.

P

The Transformation Problem and ‘Ricardian Marxism’ Prices of production are not ‘market prices,’ so we are not considering the transformation of value into a final ‘monetized’ exchange value but into an intermediate form. The specificity of this form pertains to the influence of a single mechanism on the process of price formation: the ‘redistribution’ of surplus-value which is effected by the equalization of profit rates through com peti tion.

In Marx’s theory individual capitalists do not directly appropriate the surplus-value produced by ‘their own workers’. Rather, the appropriation

Page 9: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

365 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

of surplus-value is conceived as a process of collective class exploitation, while the distribution of the aggregate (social) surplus-value among differ- ent capitals is seen as the effect of inter-capitalist competition in the sphere of circulation (which results in a tendency towards a general profit rate).

In view of this, it should be apparent that the equalization of profit rates will tend to produce a divergence between the surplus-value ‘represented’ by a particular commodity and the actual profit that can be realized through its sale. While at the aggregate level total profit ‘should’ equal total surplus value, and total value ‘should’ equal total prices of production, the differing conditions of production will mean that a divergence between value and price of production will be the norm for individual commodities. But what is meant by ‘different conditions of production’ in this connection?

Different capitals have varying ‘compositions’ - that is, they are hetero- geneous with respect to their ratios of dead to living labour. Although the ‘variable’ portion of the capital (invested in living labour) is solely capable of creating surplus-value, it is apparent that enterprises which invest a rela- tively greater portion of their capital in labour-power than in objectified means of production (‘constant’ capital) will not automatically realize more surplus-value than those that are more ‘capital-intensive’. Instead, a por- tion of the socially-produced aggregate surplus-value will become a constit- uent of the production price of a given commodity in the form of profit and in proportion to the capital invested in its production.

Accordingly, the individual capitalist will tend to receive as an increment to his invested capital not the surplus-value produced by his own workers but the profit which is due in accordance with the general rate of profit cal- culated on the capital investment: ‘When a capitalist sells his commodities a t their price of production, he recovers money in proportion to the value of the capital consumed in their production and secures profit in proportion to his advanced capital as the aliquot part of the total social capital’ (1978b: 159).

The most influential critique of Marx’s transformation procedure was elaborated by the Prussian statistician and Ricardian economist von Bort- kiewicz (1975) and popularized by Paul Sweezy (1968). For the purposes of this article it is unnecessary to review the details of the Bortkiewiczi Sweezy criticism and ‘correction’ of Marx. Suffice it to say that its point of depar- ture is that M a m failed to consider how his theoretical formula for the trans- formation of commodity values into prices of production can be reconciled with the model of ‘simple reproduction’ outlined in the second volume of Capital. Furthermore Mam’s transformation procedure is rejected because ‘it excludes the constant and variable capitals from the transformation process, whereas the principle of the equal profit rate ... must involve these elements’ (Bortkiewicz, 1975: 201). To ‘correctly’ transform commodity values into prices of production, the values of the input commodities c and v need to be transformed along with the surplus-value produced. This fun- damental premise of the BortkiewiczISweezy critique has been cogently challenged from different angles by Mage (19631, Mandel (19811, and Car- chedi (1986).

Page 10: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

366 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

For some considerable period of time the BortkiewiczISweezy ‘correction’ was criticized primarily on its own terrain of formal mathematical models, with only its ‘secondary’ premises attracting the sort of scrutiny that his more fundamental assumptions (e.g., the ‘principle’ of the ‘equal profit rate’) should have met. Consequently the debate tended to bog down in ar- guments concerning the ‘plausibility’ of assorted ‘invariance postulates’ and their variegated effects on a model which seemed congenitally resistant to a solution congenial to the maintenance of Marx’s ‘aggregate equalities’ and an equilibrium model of simple reproduction.

At first blush it seems remarkable that a follower of Ricardo like Bort- kiewicz should have been able to so thoroughly define the terms of debate surrounding the transformation issue. Ricardo’s theory of value, after all, was hardly identical to that of Marx, and his theoretical project was quite obviously very different. Unfortunately, the ‘orthodox’ tradition of Marxian political economy descending from Kautsky and Hilferding tended to under- estimate the extent of Marx’s break from the Ricardian theory of value, espe- cially at the methodological level. This orthodox school had been quite capable of disposing of the marginalist objections to Mam, as Hilferding’s rebuttal of Boehm-Bawerk showed. But faced with the Ricardian challenge of Bortkiewicz, a whole generation of Marxist economists found themselves succumbing to the subtle allure of an approach which appeared to be ‘close’ to Marx on substantive issues, while more ‘rigorous’ on technical ones. Indeed, the failure of these orthodox Marxist economists (Sweezy, 1968; Dobb, 1973; Meek, 1956; etc.) to draw an adequate methodological dividing line between Marx and Ricardo effectively led to their championing of a ‘Ri- cardian Marxism’ - and to their inability to meet the challenge of the ‘neo- Ricardianism’ elaborated by Piero Sraffa and other representatives of the British ‘Cambridge School,’ a perspective that may be succinctly termed ‘Ri- cardianism minus a labour theory of value’.

Neo-Orthodoxy and the ‘Rediscovery’ of the Value Form It was in reaction to this ‘exhaustion’ of orthodox Marxist value theory that a new interpretation of Marx appeared in the 1970s. This interpretation em- phasized the ‘critical’ character of Marx’s project and pointed to Marx’s analysis of the ‘value-form’ as an area of his value theory that had been given insufficient attention by the orthodox (Ricardian-Marxist) value theorists. One current developing out of this ‘rediscovery’ of the ‘value-form’ - a current that I designate as ‘neo-orthodox’ - has gone so far as to define Marx’s analysis of the value-form as not only the core of his theory of value, but also as a basis for rejecting his value-magnitude analysis.

Marx’s derivation of the ‘expanded’ form of value from the ‘simple’ form, of the ‘general’ form from the ‘expanded’ form, and of the ‘universal’ money form from the ‘general’ form constitutes a brilliant logico-historical unfold- ing of a result which is clearly central to his theory: ‘Money as the measure of value is the necessary form of appearance of the measure of value which is immanent in commodities, namely labour-time’ (Marx, 1977: 188). The ‘peculiarities’ of the ‘equivalent form’ to which we have already referred

Page 11: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

367 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

find final expression (both historically and logically) in the ‘money commod- ity’.

Moreover, this analysis points directly to the problem of distinguishing between the commodity’s ‘naturalhse-value’ aspect and its socio-economic or value aspect. It is hardly surprising then that Marx follows up his value- form analysis with his famous analysis of the ‘fetishism’ of commodities, which is central not only to his critique of political economy but to his cri- tique of capitalism as well. According to Marx, the forms of appearance of value lead us away from the recognition that commodities both reflect and give expression to definite social relations existing between commodity pro- ducers. Value relations systematically encourage a confusion of the natural (or the material) and the social, and it is this ‘fetishistic’ confusion which creates the illusion that, as producers, persons ‘must’ relate to one another through the mediation afforded by ‘things’.

Following his initial discussion of value as ‘socially necessary abstract labour,’ Marx’s analyses of the value-form and of commodity fetishism serve to explain his unwillingness to follow David Ricardo in immediately proceed- ing from the ‘magnitude of value as labour time’ to the ‘money-price’ of com- modities. Indeed, it is in just this way that Marx establishes his theory of value, not as a theory of price formation (after the fashion of Ricardo’s labour theory of value) but as a basis for disclosing the macrostructural processes issuing from the contradictions of the commodity form. Still, the relevance of such an investigation, as he makes clear, can only be grasped by those prepared to recognize that the product of labour can assume differ- ent (i.e. non-commodified) forms and that the social form of the division of labour need not be that of private exchange.

At one level Marx’s analysis of the ‘value-form’ and of commodity fetish- ism appears to relieve the value theorist of any obligation to address the problem of the ‘magnitude of value’ as this was traditionally conceived in Ricardian political economy. Indeed, one wing of the neo-orthodox school of value theory has conceded that the neo-Ricardian criticisms of Marx’s ‘value-magnitude analysis’ are correct and that Sraffa’s ‘physical magni- tude’ model of economic reproduction is a superior tool of macro-economic analysis (Himmelweit and Mohun, 1981; Elson, 1979). Where the ‘orthodox’ school of value theory subordinated the value-form to the value-magnitude analysis, the neo-orthodox theorists have done precisely the reverse; the only ‘continuity’ is in the dissociation of the ‘quantitative’ and ‘qualitative’ aspects of Marx’s theory.

An important consequence of the neo-orthodox preoccupation with the ‘form of value’ over the ‘magnitude of value’ is a tendency to go beyond the correct perception that ‘interaction’ occurs between production and the other ‘moments’ of reproduction (circulation, exchange, consumption) to the conclusion that, under capitalism, exchange emerges as the predorni- nant moment. Such an approach is not at all the same as saying that ‘ex- change’ is the social form of a commodity-producing economy (Rubin, 1973). Indeed, by implicitly rejecting the ontological primacy of production, it in- volves a complete evacuation of Marx’s problematic and a major concession

Page 12: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

368 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

to neo-classical marginalism as well as neo-Ricardianism. In fact, through its ‘qualitative’ focus on microeconomic exchange relations, the neo-or- thodox school of value theory draws dangerously close to the conventional economic identification of value and price. This drift is particularly evident in the following statements: ‘The transformation from Volume I [of Capi- tal] to Volume 111 is not a transformation from value to price, but from value and price considered purely from the point of view of production to value and price as modified by circulation and capitalist competition’ (Gerstein, 1986: 68). ‘I locate the creation of value not in production but at the articu- lation of production and circulation’ (De Vroey, 1981: 173). The logic of such an identification is also evident in Himmelweit and Mohun’s discussion and in that of Elson, despite occasional references to ‘value produced in produc- tion’ and the like. In this connection Lipietz’s balance sheet of the French neo-orthodox experience should be noted: the French school’s ‘failure to deal with the problem of [the] magnitude [of value] had an unexpected result: they abandoned the pole of substance and slipped irresistibly towards a purely formal and subjectivist theory of value’ (1985: 158).

Lipietz’s reference to the ‘pole of substance’ is a convenient point of de- parture for an attempt to assess the value controversy as a whole on what I call a ‘fundamentalist’ basis, i.e. a basis which recognizes the importance of both aspects of Marx’s fundamental theoretical program: the analysis of the form and the magnitude of value.

‘Fundamentalist ’ Value Theory The neo-orthodox emphasis on the value-form is associated with an attempt to clearly differentiate Marx’s notion of ‘abstract labour’ from a (Ricardian) notion of ‘embodied labour’. Indeed, many neo-orthodox theorists such as Himmelweit and Mohun (1981) regard the distinction between an ‘em- bodied-labour theory of value’ and an ‘abstract-labour theory of value’ as both the starting point and terminus of a Marxist attempt to respond to the neo-Ricardian criticisms posed by Steedman (1977)’ among others. The fun- damentalist position is that such a distinction is of vital importance, but that even if this distinction is properly made, it is still necessary to tackle the neo-Ricardian challenge head on. It is not enough to say that the neo- Ricardians have ‘misunderstood’ Marx’s theory of value; it is also necessary to demonstrate the ‘macroeconomic’ superiority of Marx’s value-magnitude analysis over the Sraffian ‘physical magnitudes’ model of the neo-Ricardi- ans.

Marx’s concept of ‘abstract labour’ is the vital conceptual nexus between his value-form and value-magnitude analyses. Since ‘abstract labor’ for Marx is the substance of value, it needs to be referred to whether one is dis- cussing the ‘qualitative’ or the ‘quantitative’ aspects of his theory of value. My contention i . ~ that in avoiding the controversy surrounding the value- magnitude analysis the proponents of the neo-orthodox school have rede- fined ‘abstract labour’ in a fashion which misrepresents Marx’s theoretical project. In their hands the concept has become a theoretical rationale for denying that value exists as an ‘objective, quantitatively determined mag-

Page 13: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

369 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

nitude’ (Hilferding, 1975: 159) and for obfuscating the processes through which value is created.

In contrast to this equivocation, the fundamentalist value theorists re- fuse to relinquish the historical-materialist principle that what transpires in exchange must be regulated and dominated by the way in which social labour time has been allocated in the sphere of production. This permits a conception of abstract labour as the reflection in thought of the real social processes through which commodities are produced for the purpose of sale and the realization of profit. Abstract labour and value now appear as the results of commodity production; both are created through the real activi- ties of producing commodities before they enter the realm of exchange.

Such an approach leads to a reinstatement of the notion of ‘socially-nec- essary labour time’ which is central to Ricardian and neo-Ricardian inter- pretations of Marx. At the same time, however, it is linked to a concept of how commodities ‘represent’ value rather than ‘embody’ abstract socially- necessary labour. This concept is well-specified by the fundamentalist theorist Anwar Shaikh: ‘It is clear in Marx ... that it is not the historical cost of a commodity in labor time, but rather its current cost of reproduction, which determines the magnitude of a commodity’s Value. As such, it is not a question of the labor time “embodied“ in a commodity but of the social cost which the current production of the commodity entails’ (1977: 113). This no- tion is basic to Shaikh’s (1977) ‘iterative’ approach to the transformation issue, as informed by the value-form analysis.

For the fundamentalists, abstract labour (as the substance of value) serves to link the value-form and value-magnitude analyses and con- sequently is measurable in two senses: a t the level of exchange or circula- tion, money appears as its sole measure; but at the level of production, the concept is conceptually apprehendedt‘measured’ in terms of labour time.

By denying that ‘abstract labour’ can be measured at the level of produc- tion in terms of ‘socially necessary labour time,’ the neo-orthodox school renders consistent their theoretical revision according to which value is created, if only in some ‘final’ sense, in e ~ c h a n g e . ~ The fundamentalists overturn this revision by explaining how the ‘form of value’ and the ‘mag- nitude of value’ are contradictory in the sense that they are conceptual re- flections of the real contradictions of commodity production: ‘... labour involved in the production of commodities produces value, while exchange merely realizes it in money-form. It is only because of this that M a m can dis- tinguish between the amounts of value and surplus-value created in com- modity production, and the generally different amounts realized through exchange’ (Shaikh, 1981: 274).

It is on the basis of this understanding of Marx’s value theory that the still-inchoate fundamentalist school has elaborated a formidable response to the neo-Ricardian/post-Sraffian challenge over such matters as the trans- formation problem, the alleged ‘redundancy’ of the value-magnitude analy- sis to a ’physical-magnitude’ analysis, and the so-called ‘joint production problem’ (Shaikh, 1977; 1981; Foley, 1986; Mandel and Freeman, 1984). Un- fortunately, so much attention has been paid to answering the ‘technical’

Page 14: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

370 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

points of the neo-Ricardians that not enough has been given to addressing the larger methodological and ontological issues that are key to differenti- ating the Marxist-fundamentalist theory from virtually every other ‘theory of value,’ Mamian and non-Marxian. It is to these issues that I shall now briefly turn.

111 METHOD AND ONTOLOGY IN MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

Reference to the distinctive methodological aspects of Marx’s theory of value is de rigueur for defenders of that theory. Dialectics are counterposed to for- mal logic; Marx’s holism (or anti-reductionism) is invoked against the methodological individualism (or ‘atomism’) of the positivist tradition; ab- straction and contradiction are located in ‘the real’ instead of being viewed as purely ‘mental’ constructs. However, helpful as these methodological principles are to an appreciation of Marx, they can contribute to a clarifica- tion of the controversy concerning value theory only to the extent that they are explicitly joined to a discussion of the ontology of social life, and in par- ticular, the ontology of ‘value’. For every ‘scientific methodology’ embraces definite ontological presuppositions, whether this is acknowledged or not; and every social theory is therefore ultimately shaped by the ontological commitments of its articulators.

In 1982 Norman Fischer published an important attempt to fashion a philosophical foundation for Elson’s neo-orthodox ‘value theory of labour’. Fischer’s basic thesis was that Marx regarded ‘abstract labour’ as an ab- stract Universal rather than as an abstract particular - as the kind of ‘general social structure’ which necessitates an ontology of ‘social, non-par- ticular entities’. Where empiricist or positivist conceptions of science are ‘two-tiered’ (admitting only general laws and particulars, and defining ‘laws pertaining to particulars’ as the primary objects of science), Marx’s onto- logical position involves a three-tiered conception in which real structures mediate laws and particulars. Importantly, Fischer noted that ‘what charac- terizes Marx’s philosophy within those that are three-tiered is its holistic interpretation of the entities mediating laws and particulars’ (1982: 30).

Within Marx’s theory there are several social-structural entities which enjoy such ‘holistic’ ontological status, among them abstract labour, value and ‘the world of commodities’. Indeed, Marx’s very procedure in the first chapter of Capital I is, as we have seen, implicitly to establish ‘value’ as a ‘general’ or ‘universal’ concept corresponding to a real social process. Marx’s ‘holistic’ commitments are rendered explicit in a passage from his appendix to the first German edition of Capital where he speaks of a ‘reversal, whereby the sensuously concrete is considered as only the form of appear- ance of the abstract universal, as opposed to the case where the abstract uni- versal is a property of the concrete’. No less than the other ‘reversals’ peculiar to the ‘equivalent form’ of value, this reversal, for Marx, ‘charac- terizes the value expression’ (1953: 271; Fischer, 1982: 31).

Marx’s observations here would seem to support the notion that abstract labour - a real structure - finds expression through the concrete particulars of the products of labour. Thus, to conceive of abstract labour as a ‘univer-

Page 15: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

371 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

sal structure’ (or, more dynamically, as a ‘universal process’) is not to deny that it findsparticular expressions or concrete forms (in which, indeed, it is apprehended as a ‘property of the concrete’); it is to insist that it has an ex- istence which is independent of these concrete particulars as well. The quan- titative dimensionality of abstract labour is, therefore, not confined to concrete particulars (the money-form), but exerts itself also at the level of its social-structural existence (as socially-necessary labour time).

In my view such a conceptualization is the implicit ontological basis of the fundamentalist account of value theory, as represented by Shaikh in particular. As we have seen, the fundamentalist account stresses the impor- tance of both the ‘magnitude of value’ and the ‘form of value’. The magni- tude-of-value problematic directs attention to the macro-level and to the measurement of value in terms of socially-necessary labour time. The form- of-value problematic directs attention to the micro-level issue of the quan- titative relation between particular commodities as expressed through the money form.

The dissociation of these problematics can only lead to a dualism of uni- versal and particular, i.e. to a denial of their dialectical unity. In practical terms such a dualism must eventuate in that methodological privileging of ‘the particular’ which is characteristic of all ‘theories of value’ which focus on the ‘individual commodity’ at the expense of an understanding of ‘the world of Commodities’. Such an approach is characteristic of Ricardo’s theory (despite his concern with the macroeconomic issue of the distribu- tion of income between classes); of Mill’s ‘cost of production’ theory; and of neo-classical marginal utility theory. ‘Orthodox’ (Ricardian) Marxist value theory is characterized by an uneasy, and ultimately untenable, compromise between a dualistic and a dialectical (monistic) handling of the univer- sal/particular relation, while neo-Ricardianism represents a bold reasser- tion of a dualistic position, but one which accords an analytical privilege to ‘macro-level’ economic phenomena (abstracted from any theory of value). Neo-orthodox Marxian value theory, in this context, can be interpreted as a reassertion of the ‘microeconomic side’ of Marx’s value theory (the func- tion of which is to ‘remind’ us that the product of labour is valorized only by virtue of the existence of determinate social relations) within a theoreti- cal space which basically accepts both a dualistic framework and a macroe- conomic analysis which eschews any ‘value-magnitude’ theory.

What needs to be stressed by the Marxist fundamentalists in relation to the neo-orthodox school is that money (that favorite neo-orthodox ‘measure of value’) becomes the form of value in its role as the universal equiualent. To cite Marx: ‘Since all other commodities are merely particular equivalents for money, the latter being their universal equivalent, they relate to money as particular commodities relate to the universal commodity’ (1977: 184). Money, as the ‘universal commodity,’ is the expression of undifferentiated abstract labour. Significantly, Marx goes on to say that ‘the money-form is merely the reflection thrown upon a single commodity by the relations be- tween all other Commodities’ (1977: 184). This can be expressed otherwise as follows: money is the form of appearance or ‘reflection’ of a structure of

Page 16: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

372 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

abstract labour which mediates the relations existing between commodities. Yet to understand this structure and its mediative role, one must look to the macro-level problem of the ‘magnitude of value’. Hence, abstract labour needs to be conceived as a structure (of relations) grounded in production but reflected by individual commodities in the sphere of circulation - and this is precisely the general position implied by the fundamentalist school of value theory. It seems to me that it is solely on this basis that the fundamental postulates of Marx’s value theory, as these were defined earlier can be sus- tained: that living labour and living labour alone is the source of all newly- produced value (including surplus-value) and that value exists as a definite quantitative magnitude at the level of the capitalist economy as a whole. In other words, what is most ‘operationally significant’ in Marx’s theory of value can be defended only on a fundamentalist and not a neo-orthodox basis.

We are now in a strong position to specify a key difference between the neo-classical (marginalist) and Marxist accounts of ‘economic value’. When the marginal-utility theorist Boehm-Bawerk (1975) argues that ‘abstract utility’ can as easily serve as the ‘common factor’ shared by all commodities as abstract labour, he begs the question of the ontological status of ‘utility’. ‘Abstract utility’ is merely a ‘mental generalization’ (Kay, 1979)’ an ideal abstraction, not a ‘real structure’ of relations. Furthermore, utility is a prop- erty of commodities which, as Marx insists, must be ‘abstracted from’ in the exchange process. The ‘use-value’ of a commodity is always a ‘particular’ use-value. This does not make it ‘irrelevant’ to the price it can fetch, but it does make it irrelevant to a specification of the larger social processes in which ‘value’ is enmeshed and which set limits on ‘purchasing power,’ prof- its and the realizability of set prices.

The methodological difference between M a n and Boehm-Bawerk, so often commented upon but inadequately defined by the ‘orthodox’ tradition of Marxian political economy, turns then on different conceptions of the on- tology of social life: Boehm-Bawerk’s positivism reflecting a profoundly nominalist outlook, Marx’s dialectical method a profoundly realist and holis- tic one. The necessary upshot of this difference is that the marginalist ac- count of value expresses an indefinite and quantitatively indeterminate relation between two incommensurable spheres: an ideal sphere of human predilections, norms and ‘rational calculations’ and a material sphere of scarce ‘economic resources’. Marx rejects such a psychologistic-naturalistic appreciation of value, insisting that the value relation is a social relation among people - a relation which forms part of a monistic reality in which the material, the social and the ideal are all ‘internally-related’ aspects of a unified totality.

IV SOME IMPLICATIONS OF MARX’S VALUE THEORY

There is, of course, no a priori basis upon which one can judge the ‘truth’ of Mam’s social ontology in relation to the nominalism and dualism which per- vades not only non-Marxist thought but much ostensibly Marxist thought as well. As Marx remarks in his second thesis on Feuerbach: ‘Man must

Page 17: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

373 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

prove the truth, i.e., the reality and power, the this-worldliness of his think- ing in practice’ (1989: 8). If the fundamental postulates of Marx’s theory of value can be sustained on the basis of a realist-holistic ontology, this in it- self does not establish the probity of that theory. Rather, it is that ontology which acquires credence to the extent that the theory and methodology that it informs demonstrate their power to explain social reality.

What then are the substantive implications of the postulates that ‘living labour is the sole source of new value’ and that ‘value exists as a definite quantitative magnitude at the macroeconomic level’? In my view they are immense, bearing on virtually every aspect of life in a capitalist society. In particular, they provide a substantial basis upon which to analyse the origins and nature of social conflict under capitalism; and, as such, they serve to radically distinguish the Marxist from the Weberian strands within the so- called ‘conflict-power paradigm’. An explicit confrontation between Marx’s ‘value-theoretical’ analysis and Weber’s marginalist-informed account of ‘p, wer’ can only result in a much-deserved implosion of this artfully-con- trived but hopelessly eclectic ‘paradigm’.

But apart from such ‘theoreticist’ considerations, the real power of these postulates derives from the fact that they breathe life into Marx’s account of the historical limits of capitalism. Together they constitute the basis of Marx’s famous ‘law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall’ - a law which Mam regarded as central both to his theory of cyclical crisis and to his ac- count of the historical-structural crisis of capitalism. In a nutshell, this law states that the tendency of the social capital to increase its organic composi- tion (i.e. to replace ‘living labour’ by the ‘dead labour’ embodied in an in- creasingly sophisticated productive apparatus) must exert a downward pressure on the rate of profit, the decisive regulator of capitalist accumula- tion (see Smith, 1991 for an extended theoretical and empirical exposition of these issues).

To be sure, Marx’s law of value is merely a ‘necessary presupposition’ of the law of the falling tendency of the rate of profit, not a sufficient one. Yet, there is a sense in which the latter stands as a corollary to the former, even if not a theoretically ineluctable one. For capitalism is the one mode of pro- duction in which the object of production is only incidentally the production of particular things to satisfy particular human wants; but in which it is directly and overwhelmingly the production of value, that ‘social substance’ which is the flesh and blood of Adam Smith’s ‘invisible hand’.

In the end, Marx’s theory of value is concerned with the historical pro- mise and fateful implications of a labour process which has assumed the so- cial form of a ‘valorization’ process. Marx’s theory serves to remind us that the imperative to ‘produce value’ is a social imperative, an imperative of capitalist social relations, not a technical or natural necessity inherent in the metabolic relation between humanity and nature. Only a society bur- dened by the need to ‘produce value’ could give birth to so absurd a phe- nomenon as a ‘crisis of overproduction’. And only such a society can transform the benefits flowing from labour-saving technological innovation into declining living standards, unemployment, bitter trade rivalries, de-

Page 18: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

374 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

pression and war. Marx’s theory of value, in sum, provides a compelling basis for the conclusion that capitalism is, at bottom, an ‘irrational’ and his- torically-limited system, one which digs its own grave by seeking to assert its ‘independence’ from living labour while remaining decisively dependent upon this labour for the production of its own life-blood: the surplus-value which is the social substance of private profit.

NOTES

In my view there is a problem with Rubin’s implicit identification of a ‘physiological ex- penditure of labor’ solely with the concrete aspect of labour. Indeed it is just this identifi- cation which lays the conceptual basis for severing ‘abstract labour’ from its real basis in the production of commodities. Here I am anticipating my critique of the neo-or- thodox school, which I contend goes rather further than Rubin in identifying abstract labour with the ‘exchange process’ (as distinct from exchange as the ‘social form’ of com- modity production). The first and third volumes of Capital appear to contradict one another because the analysis of each is predicated on theoretical assumptions based upon definite levels of abstraction (‘exchange at value’ and ‘exchange a t production price’). Neither of these as- sumptions is fundamental to Marx’s value theory in the way that the postulates that I have just identified are. It should be noted that ‘normally required labour time’ and ‘necessary labour time’ are not strictly synonymous. The difference between the two expressions points to a dy- namic element in Marx’s understanding of the process of value formation. The most ad- vanced techniques of production requiring the least expenditure of concrete labour do not immediately transform the structure of values, but they must do so eventually. Some Marxists (notably Shaikh, 1981) defend an ‘economic interpretation’ of socially- necessary labour according to which it is defined not only by production conditions but also by market conditions (a ‘demand-side’ determination). I have chosen not to pursue this particular controversy in this paper in part because its operational importance has never impressed me greatly. This neo-orthodox idea, I believe, is not shared by Rubin, though some of his arguments lend themselws to such an approach. There is an important difference between arguing that exchange ‘leaves its mark’ on the production process and effectively denying the ontological primacy of production over exchange (i.e. of content over form). Certainly, exchange mirrors changes in the standard of socially-necessary labour time required for the (re)production of commodities and therefore gives effect to changes in the structure of value/abstract-labour. But exchange (as a discrete moment of reproduction) does not itself ‘cause’ these changes. Further to Note 1 above, it should also be emphasized that it is precisely because exchange effects a process of ‘equalization of products of labor on the market’ (Himmelweit and Mohun, 1981: 235) (i.e. involves a ‘real abstraction’) that production oriented towards exchange must take account of the fact that ‘physiological labour’ is both utility-shaping and value- creating - i.e. both concrete and abstract at one and the same time.

REFERENCES

Boehm-Bawerk, Eugen von 1975 Karl Marx and the Close of His System. In Paul Sweezy (ed.), Karl Mam and

the Close of His System & Boehm-Bawerk’s Criticism of Mam. London: Merlin Press

Page 19: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

375 MARX’S THEORY OF VALUE

Bortkiewicz, Ladislaus von 1975 ‘On the Correction of Marx’s Fundamental Theoretical Construction in the

Third Volume of Capital.’ Pp. 199-221 in P. Sweezy (ed.), Karl Marx and the Close of His System & Boehm-Bawerk’s Criticism of Marx. London: Merlin Press

Carchedi, Guglielmo 1986 ‘The Logic of Prices as Values.’ Pp. 215-39 in Ben Fine (ed.), The Value

Dimension: Marx versus Ricardo and Sraffa. London: Routledge & Kugan Paul

Colletti, Lucio 1972 From Rousseau to Lenin. London: New Left Books De Vroey, Michel 1981 ‘Value, Production and Exchange.’ Pp. 173-201 in Ian Steedman et al., The

Dobb, Maurice 1973 Theories of Value and Distribution Since Adam Smith. Cambridge:

Elson, Diane 1979 ‘The Value Theory of Labour.’ Pp. 115-80 in Diane Elson (ed.), Value: The

Fine, Ben 1986 ‘Introduction.’ Pp. 1-17 in Ben Fine (ed.), The Value Dimension: Marx

Value Controversy. London: Verso

Cambridge University Press

Representation of Labour in Capitalism. London: CSE Books

Versus Ricardo and Sraffa. London and New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul

Fischer, Norman 1982 ‘The Ontology of Abstract Labor.’ Review of Radical Political Economics

Foley, Duncan 1986 Understanding Capital: Marx’s Economic Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

Gerstein, Ira 1986 ‘Production, Circulation and Value.’ Pp. 45-93 in Ben Fine (ed.), The Value

Hilferding, Rudolf 1975 Boehm-Bawerk’s Criticism of Marx. In Paul Sweezy (ed.), Karl Marx and

14(2): 27-35

University Press

Dimension. London and New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul

the Close of his System & Boehm-Bawerk’s Criticism of Marx. London: Merlin Press

Himmelweit, Susan, and Simon Mohun 1981 ‘Real Abstractions and Anomalous Assumptions.’ Pp. 224-65 in Ian

Kay, Geoffrey 1979 ‘Why Labour is the Starting Point of Capital.’ Pp. 46-66 in Diane Elson

(ed.), Value: The Representation of Labour in Capitalism. London: CSE Books

Steedman et al., The Value Controversy. London: Verso

Lipietz, Main 1985 The Enchanted World. London: Verso

Page 20: Understanding Marx's theory of value: an assessment of a controversy

376 MURRAY E.G. SMITH

Mage, Shane 1963 The Law of the Falling Tendency of the Rate of Profit. Ph.D. dissertation,

Mandel, Ernest 1981 ‘Introduction.’ Pp. 9-90 in Karl Marx, Capital Volume Three. New York:

Mandel, Ernest, and Alan Freeman (eds.) 1984 Ricardo, Marx, Sraffa. London: Verso Marx, Karl 1953 ‘Die Wortform.’ In Kleine Okonomische Schriften. Berlin: Dietz Verlag 1965 ‘Marx to L. Kugelmann in Hanover, July 11 1868.’ Pp. 208-10 in Karl Mam

Columbia University

Vintage

and Frederick Engels, Selected Correspondence. Moscow: Progress Publishers

1973 Grundrisse. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books 1975 Theories of Surplus Value, Part 1x1. Moscow: Progress 1977 Capital Volume One. New York: Vintage 1978a Theories of Surplus Value, Part I. Moscow: Progress 1978b Capital III. Moscow: Progress Publishers 1989 Readings from Karl Marx (ed. Derek Sayer). London and New York:

Meek, Ronald 1956 Studies in the Labor Theory of Value (2nd ed.). New York: Monthly Review

Press Morishima, Michio 1973 Marx’s Economics. Cambridge University Press Rubin, 1.1. 1973 Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value. Montreal: Black Rose Shaikh, Anwar 1977 ‘Marx’s Theory of Value and the “Transformation Problem”.’ Pp. 106-39 in

J. Schwartz (ed.), The Subtle Anatomy of Capitalism. Santa Monica: Goody ear

Controversy. London: Verso

Routledge

1981 ‘The Poverty of Algebra.’ Pp. 266-300 in Ian Steedman et al., The Value

Smith, Murray 1989 The Value Controversy and Social Theory: An Inquiry into Marx’s ‘Labor

Theory of Value’. Ph.D. dissertation, University of British Columbia 1991 ‘Respecifying Marx’s Value Categories: A Theoretical and Empirical

Reconsideration of the “Law of the Falling Rate of Profit”.’ Studies in Politi- cal Economy, 35, in press

Steedman, Ian 1977 Marx After Sraffa. London: New Left Books Sweezy, Paul 1968 The Theory of Capitalist Development. New York: Monthly Review Press